Results for 'Edith Ayres Copeland'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  32
    The institutional setting of Plato's republic.Edith Ayres Copeland - 1924 - International Journal of Ethics 34 (3):228-242.
  2.  16
    The Institutional Setting of Plato's Republic.Edith Ayres Copeland - 1924 - International Journal of Ethics 34 (3):228-242.
  3.  26
    What shall we do with economic science?Edith Ayres - 1938 - International Journal of Ethics 48 (2):143-164.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  6
    What Shall We Do with Economic Science?Edith Ayres - 1937 - International Journal of Ethics 48 (2):143.
  5.  9
    What Shall We Do with Economic Science?Edith Ayres - 1938 - International Journal of Ethics 48 (2):143-164.
  6.  19
    The Essential Turing.B. J. Copeland (ed.) - 2004 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Lectures, scientific papers, top secret wartime material, correspondence, and broadcasts are introduced and set in context by Jack Copeland, Director of the Turing Archive for the History of Computing."--Jacket.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  7.  28
    Tense trees: a tree system for ${\rm K}_{{\rm t}}$.B. J. Copeland - 1983 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (3):318-322.
  8.  51
    The indeterminacy of computation.Nir Fresco, B. Jack Copeland & Marty J. Wolf - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):12753-12775.
    Do the dynamics of a physical system determine what function the system computes? Except in special cases, the answer is no: it is often indeterminate what function a given physical system computes. Accordingly, care should be taken when the question ‘What does a particular neuronal system do?’ is answered by hypothesising that the system computes a particular function. The phenomenon of the indeterminacy of computation has important implications for the development of computational explanations of biological systems. Additionally, the phenomenon lends (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  36
    The making of the dull, deficient and backward pupil in British elementary education 1870–1914.Ian Copeland - 1996 - British Journal of Educational Studies 44 (4):377-394.
    Michel Foucault's concept of normalisation is taken as a basis to explore the factors involved in the identification of dull, deficient and backward pupils in British Elementary Education between 1870 and 1914. Normalisation consists of the five processes of comparison, differentiation, hierarchisation, homogenisation and exclusion. These processes operate through dividing practices which distribute groups socially and are supported in this work by scientific ideas. In this instance, the norm of the intellect is the basis of the dividing practices. The empirical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  8
    The Essential Turing: Seminal Writings in Computing, Logic, Philosophy, Artificial Intelligence, and Artificial Life P Lus the Secrets of Enigma.B. Jack Copeland (ed.) - 2004 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    Alan Turing, pioneer of computing and WWII codebreaker, is one of the most important and influential thinkers of the twentieth century. In this volume for the first time his key writings are made available to a broad, non-specialist readership. They make fascinating reading both in their own right and for their historic significance: contemporary computational theory, cognitive science, artificial intelligence, and artificial life all spring from this ground-breaking work, which is also rich in philosophical and logical insight.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  21
    Special Educational Needs and the Education Reform Act, 1988.Ian Copeland - 1991 - British Journal of Educational Studies 39 (2):190 - 206.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  10
    The Establishment of Models of Education for Disabled Children.Ian C. Copeland - 1995 - British Journal of Educational Studies 43 (2):179-200.
    The concept of social reproduction of sets of advantages and disadvantages together with that of status group, is used to explore the evidence and thinking presented in the Royal Commission on the Blind, the Deaf and Dumb, etc. regarding the education of children with disabilities in 1889. Even though the evidence was ambiguous, models for the education of children with disabilities were laid down. Integration into mainstream elementary schools was recommended for the blind. Recommendations for deaf children were divided in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  7
    The Promise of Modern Life: An Interrelational View.John W. Copeland - 1958 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 19 (4):547-547.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Self-trust and critical thinking online: a relational account.Lavinia Marin & Samantha Marie Copeland - 2022 - Social Epistemology.
    An increasingly popular solution to the anti-scientific climate rising on social media platforms has been the appeal to more critical thinking from the user's side. In this paper, we zoom in on the ideal of critical thinking and unpack it in order to see, specifically, whether it can provide enough epistemic agency so that users endowed with it can break free from enclosed communities on social media (so called epistemic bubbles). We criticise some assumptions embedded in the ideal of critical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  25
    Computation.B. Jack Copeland - 2004 - In Luciano Floridi (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 1–17.
    The prelims comprise: The Birth of the Modern Computer What is a Turing Machine? The Basic Operations of a Turing Machine Human Computation The Church—Turing Thesis Beyond the Universal Turing Machine Misunderstandings of the Church—Turing Thesis: The Limits of Machines Conclusion.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  11
    Philosophy and Genius:Characters and Events John Dewey, Joseph Ratner.C. E. Ayres - 1930 - International Journal of Ethics 40 (2):263-.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  52
    Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology. [REVIEW]C. E. Ayres - 1922 - Journal of Philosophy 19 (17):469-475.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   255 citations  
  18. The Church-Turing Thesis.B. Jack Copeland - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    There are various equivalent formulations of the Church-Turing thesis. A common one is that every effective computation can be carried out by a Turing machine. The Church-Turing thesis is often misunderstood, particularly in recent writing in the philosophy of mind.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  19.  6
    Une lecture pragmatiste des parcs éoliens citoyens en Frise du Nord.Edith Chezel - 2020 - Multitudes 77 (4):78-87.
    La proposition de cet article est de se saisir du « temps de l’expérience » des parcs éoliens citoyens en Frise du Nord (Allemagne) en le confrontant à la fois aux pulsations politiques des expérimentations techniques et à la fois aux rythmes des vents, comme ce qui permettrait d’en prendre soin, pour penser la continuité des épreuves de transition dans le temps mais aussi dans l’espace, dans une perspective démocratique de multiplication des expériences de transition.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Artificial Intelligence: A Philosophical Introduction.Jack Copeland - 1993 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    Presupposing no familiarity with the technical concepts of either philosophy or computing, this clear introduction reviews the progress made in AI since the inception of the field in 1956. Copeland goes on to analyze what those working in AI must achieve before they can claim to have built a thinking machine and appraises their prospects of succeeding. There are clear introductions to connectionism and to the language of thought hypothesis which weave together material from philosophy, artificial intelligence and neuroscience. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  21. What is computation?B. Jack Copeland - 1996 - Synthese 108 (3):335-59.
    To compute is to execute an algorithm. More precisely, to say that a device or organ computes is to say that there exists a modelling relationship of a certain kind between it and a formal specification of an algorithm and supporting architecture. The key issue is to delimit the phrase of a certain kind. I call this the problem of distinguishing between standard and nonstandard models of computation. The successful drawing of this distinction guards Turing's 1936 analysis of computation against (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  22.  19
    Embedding Justice Considerations in Climate Resilience.Jose Carlos Cañizares-Gaztelu, Samantha Copeland & Neelke Doorn - 2023 - Ethics, Policy and Environment (1):63-88.
    This article contributes to recent work on justice in resilience-based projects for climate adaptation. At present, the model commonly used for guiding normative reflection in this domain is the tripartite model of justice, whereby justice is seen as comprising distributive, procedural and recognitional aspects. After discussing some conceptual problems and practical shortcomings of this model, we propose an alternative model with six forms of justice or kinds of justice demands: distributive, procedural, intergenerational, restorative and retributive justice, and justice in system (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  8
    Anyone but him: The complexity of precluding an alternative.Edith Hemaspaandra, Lane A. Hemaspaandra & Jörg Rothe - 2007 - Artificial Intelligence 171 (5-6):255-285.
  24.  11
    Processing Code-Switches in the Presence of Others: An ERP Study.Edith Kaan, Souad Kheder, Ann Kreidler, Aleksandra Tomić & Jorge R. Valdés Kroff - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  30
    I—Michael Ayres.Michael Ayres - 2001 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75 (1):91-110.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  39
    What is realism?: Michael Ayres.Michael Ayres - 2001 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75 (1):91–110.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  19
    What Is Realism?: Michael Ayres.Michael Ayres - 2001 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 75 (1):91-110.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. The genesis of possible worlds semantics.B. Jack Copeland - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (2):99-137.
    This article traces the development of possible worlds semantics through the work of: Wittgenstein, 1913-1921; Feys, 1924; McKinsey, 1945; Carnap, 1945-1947; McKinsey, Tarski and Jónsson, 1947-1952; von Wright, 1951; Becker, 1952; Prior, 1953-1954; Montague, 1955; Meredith and Prior, 1956; Geach, 1960; Smiley, 1955-1957; Kanger, 1957; Hintikka, 1957; Guillaume, 1958; Binkley, 1958; Bayart, 1958-1959; Drake, 1959-1961; Kripke, 1958-1965.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  29. Hypercomputation.B. Jack Copeland - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (4):461-502.
  30. All of the Women of the Bible.Edith Deen - 1955
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31. Dusing, Edith und Klein, H.-D.(Hrsg.), Geist und Literatur.Edith Brugmans - 2009 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 71 (2):429.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. On when a semantics is not a semantics: Some reasons for disliking the Routley-Meyer semantics for relevance logic.B. J. Copeland - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):399-413.
  33. The Turing test.B. Jack Copeland - 2000 - Minds and Machines 10 (4):519-539.
    Turing''s test has been much misunderstood. Recently unpublished material by Turing casts fresh light on his thinking and dispels a number of philosophical myths concerning the Turing test. Properly understood, the Turing test withstands objections that are popularly believed to be fatal.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  34. Artificial Intelligence: A Philosophical Introduction.B. Jack Copeland - 1993 - Cambridge: Blackwell.
    Presupposing no familiarity with the technical concepts of either philosophy or computing, this clear introduction reviews the progress made in AI since the inception of the field in 1956. Copeland goes on to analyze what those working in AI must achieve before they can claim to have built a thinking machine and appraises their prospects of succeeding.There are clear introductions to connectionism and to the language of thought hypothesis which weave together material from philosophy, artificial intelligence and neuroscience. John (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  35.  62
    On serendipity in science: discovery at the intersection of chance and wisdom.Samantha Copeland - 2019 - Synthese 196 (6):2385-2406.
    Abstract‘Serendipity’ is a category used to describe discoveries in science that occur at the intersection of chance and wisdom. In this paper, I argue for understanding serendipity in science as an emergent property of scientific discovery, describing an oblique relationship between the outcome of a discovery process and the intentions that drove it forward. The recognition of serendipity is correlated with an acknowledgment of the limits of expectations about potential sources of knowledge. I provide an analysis of serendipity in science (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36.  11
    Effects of State Anxiety on Selective Processing of Threatening Information.Edith Chen - 1996 - Cognition and Emotion 10 (3):225-240.
  37.  17
    What Is Realism?Michael Ayres - 2001 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75:91-110.
    A scholastic-Cartesian schema faithfully maps ordinary, effective ways of dealing with intentionality; yet its apparent incoherence provokes philosophers into opting for one of two stances, 'Cartesian' or 'direct realist', seemingly incompatible, yet each seem in accord with ordinary thought. A wide range of canonical and current theories, realist, idealist and hybrid, essentially involve one option or the other. We should instead consider why the language of intentionality, with its apparent anomalies, works so well. Released from the obligation to opt for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38. On serendipity in science: discovery at the intersection of chance and wisdom.Samantha M. Copeland - 2017 - Synthese (6):1-22.
    ‘Serendipity’ is a category used to describe discoveries in science that occur at the intersection of chance and wisdom. In this paper, I argue for understanding serendipity in science as an emergent property of scientific discovery, describing an oblique relationship between the outcome of a discovery process and the intentions that drove it forward. The recognition of serendipity is correlated with an acknowledgment of the limits of expectations about potential sources of knowledge. I provide an analysis of serendipity in science (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  39.  16
    Young Children with ASD Use Lexical and Referential Information During On-line Sentence Processing.Edith L. Bavin, Evan Kidd, Luke A. Prendergast & Emma K. Baker - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
  40.  9
    Introduction.Ian Ayres, Abbe R. Gluck & Kate Stith - 2018 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 46 (2):201-202.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  12
    Hybrid Elections Broaden Complexity-Theoretic Resistance to Control.Edith Hemaspaandra, Lane A. Hemaspaandra & Jörg Rothe - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (4):397-424.
    Electoral control refers to attempts by an election's organizer to influence the outcome by adding/deleting/partitioning voters or candidates. The important paper of Bartholdi, Tovey, and Trick [1] that introduces control proposes computational complexity as a means of resisting control attempts: Look for election systems where the chair's task in seeking control is itself computationally infeasible.We introduce and study a method of combining two or more candidate-anonymous election schemes in such a way that the combined scheme possesses all the resistances to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Narrow Versus Wide Mechanism: Including a Re-Examination of Turing’s Views on the Mind-Machine Issue.B. Jack Copeland - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (1):5-32.
  43. Accelerating Turing machines.B. Jack Copeland - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (2):281-300.
    Accelerating Turing machines are Turing machines of a sort able to perform tasks that are commonly regarded as impossible for Turing machines. For example, they can determine whether or not the decimal representation of contains n consecutive 7s, for any n; solve the Turing-machine halting problem; and decide the predicate calculus. Are accelerating Turing machines, then, logically impossible devices? I argue that they are not. There are implications concerning the nature of effective procedures and the theoretical limits of computability. Contrary (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  44. The Essential Turing.B. Jack Copeland - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):541-542.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  45. Plato: The Collected Dialogues.Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns (eds.) - 1961 - Princeton: New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
  46.  19
    Levinas Between Ethics and Politics.Edith Wyschogrod - 2001 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 15 (1):66-68.
  47. Do Accelerating Turing Machines Compute the Uncomputable?B. Jack Copeland & Oron Shagrir - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (2):221-239.
    Accelerating Turing machines have attracted much attention in the last decade or so. They have been described as “the work-horse of hypercomputation” (Potgieter and Rosinger 2010: 853). But do they really compute beyond the “Turing limit”—e.g., compute the halting function? We argue that the answer depends on what you mean by an accelerating Turing machine, on what you mean by computation, and even on what you mean by a Turing machine. We show first that in the current literature the term (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  48. The Inconceivable Popularity of Conceivability Arguments.Douglas I. Campbell, Jack Copeland & Zhuo-Ran Deng - 2017 - Philosophical Quarterly 67 (267):223-240.
    Famous examples of conceivability arguments include (i) Descartes’ argument for mind-body dualism, (ii) Kripke's ‘modal argument’ against psychophysical identity theory, (iii) Chalmers’ ‘zombie argument’ against materialism, and (iv) modal versions of the ontological argument for theism. In this paper, we show that for any such conceivability argument, C, there is a corresponding ‘mirror argument’, M. M is deductively valid and has a conclusion that contradicts C's conclusion. Hence, a proponent of C—henceforth, a ‘conceivabilist’—can be warranted in holding that C's premises (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. The broad conception of computation.Jack Copeland - 1997 - American Behavioral Scientist 40 (6):690-716.
    A myth has arisen concerning Turing's paper of 1936, namely that Turing set forth a fundamental principle concerning the limits of what can be computed by machine - a myth that has passed into cognitive science and the philosophy of mind, to wide and pernicious effect. This supposed principle, sometimes incorrectly termed the 'Church-Turing thesis', is the claim that the class of functions that can be computed by machines is identical to the class of functions that can be computed by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  50.  83
    Deviant encodings and Turing’s analysis of computability.B. Jack Copeland & Diane Proudfoot - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (3):247-252.
    Turing’s analysis of computability has recently been challenged; it is claimed that it is circular to analyse the intuitive concept of numerical computability in terms of the Turing machine. This claim threatens the view, canonical in mathematics and cognitive science, that the concept of a systematic procedure or algorithm is to be explicated by reference to the capacities of Turing machines. We defend Turing’s analysis against the challenge of ‘deviant encodings’.Keywords: Systematic procedure; Turing machine; Church–Turing thesis; Deviant encoding; Acceptable encoding; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000